Noah Smith has a really nice piece
about when a microfounded model does or does not violate the Lucas critique. (See
also this useful post
from Bruegel.) Noah suggests that this comes down to a judgement call, which in
turn introduced a potential ideological bias. I want to elaborate, and suggest
another bias that may result: a bias towards simplicity. However I also want to
suggest a further bias that potentially undercuts the methodological rationale
behind microfoundations.
The key idea behind the Lucas critique was that models
should be derived from ’deep’ parameters, like agents preferences or
technological parameters. These were parameters that could reasonably be
described as independent of the way monetary policy was conducted. The target
of the Lucas critique was models where expectations formation was implicit in
the model’s equations: even if you only half believed in rational expectations,
changes in how monetary policy was done would change how expectations were
formed, and therefore change those equations.
Noah argues that whether a parameter is independent of
policy is essentially a judgement – our evidence base is not good enough to
show us one way or another. Where you have judgement, various biases, including
ideological views, can get in. I think this is right, but I also suspect the
point will not bother most macroeconomists too much. They are – rightly or
wrongly – fairly happy with treating preference parameters as exogenous,
whereas treating expectations processes as independent of policy seems clearly
problematic. (I appeal here to what most macroeconomists will think, and not
what is right. In a recent post, for example, I argue that people’s preferences
over which party to vote for are pretty malleable.)
However, once you go beyond the very simple RBC type models,
the range of deep parameters extends beyond preferences and technology. To take
the obvious example, if you want to have something useful to say about monetary
policy, you need sticky prices, and these are usually microfounded in terms of
Calvo contracts. The deep parameter in Calvo contracts is the probability that
a firm’s price will change each period. Is this parameter independent of
monetary policy?
The paper by Chari
et al to which Noah refers puts the same point in a slightly different way. If
the parameters of the model are not deep (independent), then the implied shocks
to the model will not be ‘structural’ i.e. identifiable and independent of
policy. They look at the shock processes typically included in New Keynesian
models, and split them into two groups: potentially structural shocks, which
include technology shocks, and dubiously structural shocks, which include
mark-up shocks.
How do Chari et al decide which of these two categories
shocks should be classified in? Noah would say judgement, whereas the authors
would say microeconomic evidence. However this is not a debate I want to get
into, interesting
though it is. Instead I want to agree with Chari et al: the shocks in New
Keynesian models are pretty dubious, and their deep parameters, like the Calvo
parameter, are not obviously invariant to policy.
So why do New Keynesian models contain problematic features
like Calvo contracts? Calvo contracts are a ‘trick’, by which I mean a device
that allows you to get sticky prices into a model in a reasonably tractable
way. Doing this job ‘properly’ might involve adding menu costs into the model,
but this quickly gets intractable. So Calvo contracts are a trick that acts ‘as
if’ firms were faced by menu costs. But whether this trick works – whether
Calvo contracts really do mimic what an otherwise intractable model with menu
costs would show – is inevitably a
judgement call.
Because these judgement calls are problematic, there is a
bias towards avoiding them by keeping the model simple. Here Chari et al are
explicit. “One tradition, which we prefer, is to keep the model very simple,
keep the number of parameters small and well-motivated by micro facts, and put
up with the reality that such a model neither can nor should fit most aspects
of the data. Such a model can still be very useful in clarifying how to think
about policy.”
Suppose we do not
follow this tradition, and instead attempt to explain more aspects of the data
by building models that incorporate dubious judgement calls. I think we then
have to recognise that these judgement calls will be influenced not just by the
microeconomic evidence, or ideology as Noah suggests, but also
on the need to have models that explain the real world. That is I believe a
quite reasonable thing to do, but as Chari et al point out it does mean
potentially compromising the internally consistency of the model (and therefore
its immunity from the Lucas critique). As I have argued at length elsewhere (article, working paper), microfounded models have become
dominant because they have let the evidence influence model structure through a
back door. Individual equations may no longer be selected by directly
confronting the data, but the data has influenced the judgemental calls
involved in the microfoundations.
Thanks, Simon!!
ReplyDeleteYou may be interested in this other post, in which I argue that the simplicity bias may act as a political bias too (since economies with no role for govt. tend to be simpler): http://noahpinionblog.blogspot.com/2012/02/are-macroeconomic-methods-politically.html
The 'microfoundations debate' appears to be another manifestation of the 'agent-structure debate' that has been going on in the social sciences.
ReplyDeleteTo quote Wendt..."..."micro-macro" problems...reflect the same meta-theoretical imperative - the need to adopt, for the purpose of explaining social behaviour, some conceptualization of the ontological and explanatory relationship between...agents...and societal structures".
Anywho, whilst I fancy myself a bit of a behavioural guy, I think one mustn't forget the importance of simplicity/abstraction. After all, It was only once the physiocrats invented the concept of an 'economy' as distinct from politics and society, that the very idea of economic theory was made possible.