Winner of the New Statesman SPERI Prize in Political Economy 2016


Tuesday 6 December 2022

Why Voting under FPTP should always be tactical

 

Ever since I can remember, I have advocated tactical voting. This post tries to make that argument in the context of different motivations for voting. As this is not my area of expertise please let me know of anything I have missed.  


Why do people vote? Do we vote in an instrumental way to (help) achieve some outcome, or do we vote in an expressive way to say (often just to ourselves) something about our own views. From my own experience in talking to people, many do vote in an expressive way. Even where the effective choice in a First Past The Post (FPTP) seat is between just two parties (X and Y), and where the voter happily acknowledges that on all counts X is a better choice than Y on all issues they care about (X>Y), you will often hear people say that they still couldn’t vote for X because of their policy on one particular issue. It doesn’t seem to matter that Y has the same policy as X, they nevertheless choose either not to vote at all, or vote for another party that doesn’t have that particular policy, rather than vote for X, even though X>Y and only X or Y can win


This attitude makes little sense (but see below) if voting is instrumental, but does make sense if voting is expressive. There was an even more extreme case of this in the last UK General Election, where some people suggested to me that they couldn’t vote for Labour because Labour was not formally in favour of continuing EU membership, or they didn’t trust Corbyn on Brexit. They would vote LibDem or some other party instead, even if they were in a marginal Lab/Con constituency. It was more extreme because it was almost inevitable that Brexit would happen if Johnson won, while it was far from inevitable that it would happen if Johnson didn’t win, even if, as I suggested here, Labour got an overall majority. In this case people were voting in a way that, from an instrumental point of view, would make them worse off.


Expressive voting is one reason why it makes sense for the opposition parties under FPTP to not field candidates in seats they have no chance of winning in the next election. Even if the parties cooperate informally, there is nothing stopping expressive voters voting for the party closest to their own views even when that party has no chance of winning. I’ve seen it argued that such actions by political parties are bad because it ‘reduces voters choice’, but in reality it only reduces the choice of expressive voters. Unsurprisingly, as most party members are likely to be instrumental in their attitudes, most Labour members (e.g see this poll) would favour not putting up candidates in seats where doing so might split the anti-Tory vote. From an instrumental point of view, this majority is entirely correct.


Instrumental voting is very different from expressive voting. If voting is instrumental, it makes sense for your vote to have some purpose beyond self statement, which usually means voting for party X even if you don’t agree with everything X stands for, simply because the realistic choice is between X and Y and you prefer X to Y. In most cases (but see below) instrumental voters will vote tactically, because that is the most effective way of using their vote.


However instrumental voting is subject to a problem that is often called the ‘paradox of voting’. The problem is the chances that your vote influences the outcome are negligible. To use the language of economics which is quite descriptive, the voter is ‘small’ relative to the electorate in a constituency, so their own vote is hardly ever critical in deciding the result. The ‘paradox of voting’ could also be called the insignificance of the individual voter argument, where insignificance means very small indeed. Note that this paradox only applies to instrumental voting, and not expressive voting.


I remember one General Election trying to persuade someone to vote LibDem in a LibDem/Con marginal. They objected that it was a waste of their time because their vote would be insignificant, but they did it just to please me. The LibDem candidate ended up winning by 10 votes. I triumphantly said to the person I had persuaded to vote, look your vote did matter, to only be told that if they hadn’t voted the LibDem candidate would still have won by 9 votes, so it was they who had been proved right.


Instrumental voting can be rescued from this insignificance paradox by talking about the payoff from your side winning. If the benefit to you of the party you vote for winning is sufficiently large, this can offset in expected benefit terms the very low possibility of your vote being decisive. However that is not the route I want to go down. Instead I have a more fundamental problem with the paradox of voting.


The insignificance of the individual voter argument casts voting in individualistic, expected utility terms. I think that is the wrong way to look at it. Voting is instead a social activity. We can see that quite simply from the fact that large numbers of people do vote in an instrumental way, despite their individual insignificance, so either they are being irrational or there is something else going on. As economists like to think that most people are not irrational I think we can conclude that something else is going on.


You can see why there is a social norm that we should try and vote from imagining a contest between two parties, one of which had rational policies and the other had irrational policies. Rational people prefer the rational party and vice versa. As most people are rational, the rational party should win, but if all rational people decided it was irrational to vote because of the paradox of voting, the irrational party would win, and the rational people would be worse off. Whilst the insignificance of the individual voter argument works for the individual alone, it does not generalise to society. [1] It may not make sense voting as an individual, but as part of society (or as a member of a class) it certainly does. There is evidence that most people do see it as a social duty to vote.


Seen in this light, as I think it should, expressive voting becomes a rather selfish act when voting is done secretly. You vote to make yourself feel better about yourself, rather than for the good of society as a whole. It also follows that we should vote for the party that would make society (or a group of that society like a class) as a whole better, rather than voting for the party that would make ourselves individually better off. This is because the latter is voting based on the outcome for one individual, where the paradox of voting still applies.


If we should vote instrumentally to make society (in our personal view) better, then it almost follows automatically that tactical voting under FPTP is the only sensible way to vote. By the same logic, you will often, under FPTP, end up voting for the lesser evil, because even if there is a party you could vote for that is better than the lesser evil, voting for it will be a wasted vote because that party cannot win. If you don’t like voting for the lesser evil that probably means either you prefer expressive voting or you don’t like FPTP systems..


Why do I say that it almost follows automatically? There are two common arguments against voting tactically, which in particular (and I would say pretty exceptional) circumstances are valid. The first arises from voting being a repeated activity (a repeated game). This brings in the possibility that voting one way today may influence our choice in the next election. Suppose X>Y, but X is still pretty awful, and if X lost this time it might be replaced by Z, where Z>X>Y and Z was a lot better than X. In those circumstances the best social choice might be to allow X to lose, because it would allow Z to emerge next time (see here).


This is a way you can try and rationalise why some of those on the right of the Labour party, for example, might have worked to enable Corbyn to lose in 2019, because they believed that would allow a much better Labour party to emerge from the ashes of his defeat that wouldn’t have emerged if Labour had won.


The problems with this argument come from both the many ifs involved and from the present sacrifice made (party Y gets to rule badly for 5 years). The many ifs include whether defeat for X does lead to Z, and whether Z would have happened even if X had won, and that Z will win against Y in 5 years time. (The problems are intensified if during that 5 years party Y changes the rules of the game to make a future victory for Z less likely.) The argument has some similarities to accelerationism, which argues that the best way to achieve a 'good society' in the future is to intensify rather than try to ameliorate the current bad features of society. In my view it’s an argument that is not always wrong, but most of the time it is. On the particular example of the Labour right and Corbyn, I think the cost of a hard Brexit should pretty well dominate any perceived advantages that the Labour right might have imagined getting their party back might involve.


A second argument against tactical voting goes like this. If voters make their vote for party X conditional on X adopting some policy, then voters have some power over policy. If instead they always vote for X, they have no power. However, for this power to have any credible influence on party X, individuals have to be prepared not to vote for X if X doesn’t adopt their policy. It then becomes an argument like the one above but related to individual policies rather than party leadership or complete parties. (Because people didn’t vote for X because of some policy, X does badly and is forced to adopt the policy in the next election.)


The main problem with this argument is credibility: on most issues most voters for X will not be prepared to carry out the threat of not voting for X if they don’t get their way. For that reason most of the time those that do make this threat will be ignored. Equally there are very few issues where enough people can make common cause to pose a sufficient threat to X. But just occasionally the argument might work if the issue is central enough, voters feel strongly enough and they have a means to demonstrate the threat. The run up to the 2019 election provides one possible example, where the policy was Labour’s position on a second referendum. Voters who would normally vote for Labour voted against them in local and EU elections, and threatened to not vote for them in general election polls, and this did change Labour’s policy on a second referendum, for better or worse.


Putting these two exceptions against tactical voting aside, I want to end by saying something about responsibility. If voting is a social norm or duty, then with that goes the idea of responsibility for outcomes. (I’m indebted to @spinninghugo for thinking about this, although he has no responsibility for my current views!) If we go back to my example of people who voted LibDem (say) in a Lab/Con marginal because they didn’t trust Corbyn on Brexit, in what sense if any are they responsible for what Johnson’s government subsequently did?


The first and obvious point is that they share that responsibility with everyone who didn’t vote tactically against the Conservatives in 2019, and those who voted for the Conservatives have a greater responsibility. However pointing this out does not avoid the issue of responsibility. To see why, imagine someone was murdered by 100 people, each of whom struck once with a dagger. You would certainly say that each of the 100 was responsible for the death of the victim, and the fact that ‘he would have died anyway even if I hadn’t been one of the 100’ doesn’t absolve anyone of their responsibility for the murder. Suppose you were not one of the 100, but had the opportunity of trying to prevent the murder, but had chosen not to. You too would have some responsibility for allowing the murder to happen. It remains the case that anyone who didn’t vote tactically against the Conservatives in 2019 remains in some small way partly responsible for things the Conservative government did that Labour would not have done.


In contrast, as tactical voting is the choice of the lesser evil, it is not the case that the voter is responsible (among millions) for everything the winning party does. Instead they are just responsible for what the winning party does differently from the only credible alternative party (X-Y in implemented policy space, if that helps).


What the only credible alternative party would have done is a counterfactual, so it allows people to try and avoid responsibility by making claims about that counterfactual. It is why, for example, those who supported the Conservatives in 2019 like to make the unlikely claim that a Corbyn led government would have been even worse than a Johnson et al government, because otherwise they would bear some responsibility for the mess we are currently in. The fact that people make such incredible claims shows that the idea that voting is a choice we should be responsible for has some force. 



[1] To drill down a little more, the paradox of voting assumes that your action of not voting is peculiar to you, and will not be followed by anyone else. If instead you assume that other people will make the same calculation as you do, then you would want to vote to avoid the irrational party always winning. More generally social norms that voting is part of being a good citizen can be seen as a social response to the paradox of voting.


.


9 comments:

  1. Remember that one third of the electorate did not vote at the last general election. Why?

    ReplyDelete
  2. What if we elaborate the idea of the repeated game? For the great majority of us who are not facing our final election, voting will be a repeated activity. Cannot my vote today have some effect on future elections, by giving future political strategists information about the policy-rhetorical changes needed to secure my vote the next time out?

    ReplyDelete
  3. My response to the paradox of voting has always been that by contributing to statistical results, you move the needle of parties' strategic thinking, even if it doesn't affect the headline outcome this time round. For example, the Greens have no chance of winning, but by voting for them, every spad will see that small-but-significant group when they do their detailed analysis. As a Green voter I would not want the Conservatives to win, but Conservative analysts will see the "Teal" results in Australia, and a small but growing Green vote could be perceived as a threat. That could persuade them to try to win a majority by appealing to Greens, bypassing traditional Labour voters. For the Green voter that's a policy win, without "winning" any actual elections.

    Australia of course doesn't have FPTP so the core issue doesn't arise, but it does also make this process more obvious, even formal. Before each election the big parties negotiate with the smaller ones for preference deals, trading off policy concessions in exchange for putting themselves somewhat higher up the list. You can be sure the minor parties trumpet those concessions when they happen. The same thing does happen under FPTP, but it's more subtle and secretive.

    From a utility maximiser point of view, the payoff is relatively small. It dominates when Z ≫ X ≅ Y, and that's not unusual in a healthy two-party system where the major parties converge. Of course, the UK today is not such an example, and in practice you're completely right that tactical voting is imperative. Also, of course, the argument is too obscure to persuade anyone - most people indeed vote in an "expressive" way. It's just the argument I keep in my back pocket in case I get into a nerd-fight with someone bringing up the paradox of voting.

    ReplyDelete
  4. I think the repeated nature of elections is important, as I the signalling aspect. For this, I would point to the impact UKIP voters had.

    Those who didn't vote tactically but still voted for UKIP may have won zero seats but by having the ability to deny seats, even from those candidates sympathetic to their position, they secured a referendum and ultimately Brexit.

    Personally, I am a Liberal. I will vote for the Liberal Democrats and whether or not they win I will be sending a signal (a small one) that the country has Liberal values and that there are votes in expressing those values. However dead or not Rexit is from an electoral perspective, there will always be new issues and new questions where I want politicians to adopt a collaborative, internationalist stance and to step away from nationalism. Sending that signal is the most important thing to me in most elections. Only in very rare elections like 2019 might I consider that any immediate rewards from tactical voting are more important than the longer term bigger trends over decades. As it was I was voting in a safe seat, so tactical voting had little value anyway, but had I been in a marginal seat I would have had some serious decisions to make.

    ReplyDelete
  5. I am on two minds about this. Most of your argument is persuasive, but I think the missing factor is that this has to be scaled to the probability of the election being close. Certainly, if the election is expected to be on a knife's edge, it makes absolute sense to vote tactically and instrumentally. But the benefits change if the election is not expected to be close. If it's the case that even if a third party is entirely annihilated, your party of choice still won't win, then the instrumental argument is much weaker. You might have a responsibility to grab a bucket and bail out water from a flooding dinghy, but no one can blame the passengers of the titanic for not doing the same.

    On the flip side, expressive voting is more powerful if the election is not close. If the party of your choice is certain to be defeated anyway, and from a policy point of view this makes no difference, then a *crushing* defeat can be in the interests of the expressive voter. A relatively close defeat can be a message in favour of the status quo, especially if it's better than "expected", whereas a major defeat will much more likely force a significant re-alignment. If nothing else, because a lot of the allies of the disliked leader will be removed from parliament...

    Certainly, as someone who didn't like Corbyn very much, the events of 2017 put a bad taste in my mouth. That defeat-which-was-treated-like-a-victory, fueled in part by lib dem voters voting for Corbyn tactically, ended up merely giving Corbyn license to double down on his ambiguous stance on Brexit and miscellanous other incompetencies. One can imagine an alternate state of the world where Corbyn decisively lost in 2017, was replaced by someone else, and so right now we are being run by a Labour government.

    ReplyDelete
  6. Regular reader. Generally consider you to be one of the most clear minded thinkers amongst conventional economists.
    On this matter I completely disagree with the whole premise of the argument.
    Arguing for workarounds in a voting system which is institutionally anti-democratic makes you an enabler rather than a force to resolve underlying issues.
    FPTP is the problem, not the people forced to use it.
    Pick up dozens of millions of votes. Stack them up in a couple of nice litle categories "Expressive" "Instrumental" et presto! We have a pseudo-argument!
    Is First Pass The Post a truly democratic way to choose a Government? Well... the author does concede implicitly it is large pile of garbaggio but hey! Why ask why? Drink Bud Light!
    What about internal beliefs? What about individual liberty to express ones ideas? What about the democratic will of the people... noise to entertain deluded imbeciles presumably...

    ReplyDelete
  7. If people were properly educated to understand what they were voting for, they would also understand why they vote the way they do. In a recent election an interviewer asked people Identified as Tory voters, in the street of solid Tory constituency, whether they agreed with the policies read out to them, then asked who stood for them, were surprised to see they agreed with Jeremy Corbyn. In my view I have always ascertained that most people have no idea of what they are voting for. Which is the way the establishment like it, and why they attack anyone that tells the truth about our system of government and policies, hence the character assassination of Tony Benn and Jeremy Corbyn. This has always been obvious but people are deliberately kept ignorant, power is tightly reigned in to support the minority against the rest. Educators of course have the responsibility to honestly transmit accurate and information with integrity, which is sadly lacking in today's world, where Universities for example are beholden to corporate sponsors for extra funding.

    ReplyDelete
  8. Thanks Simon.

    I agree with everything you say here.

    I would only add that if you are in the fortunate position of living in a safe seat where, of X and Y, your preferred choice is a racing certainty to win, if you prefer the policies of Z to either, you are absolved of the responsibility to vote for X.

    In that situation, it is better to vote for Z, in that it "sends a message" to X that their policy platform should be closer to Z. Obviously, there is a risk here of miscalculating the probability of X winning, but that is true of tactical voting in 3-way split consitutencies, too.

    I wholeheartedly agree with your position on responsibility for outcomes. I'm always bemused by anyone who thinks that their democratic responsibility begins and ends at the ballot box rather than the outcomes driven by their choices.

    ReplyDelete
  9. Two reactions.

    The first is that these arguments turn hostility to tactical voting into an argument for proportional representation. I agree totally.

    The second is that you ignore the situation in constituencies where no challenger has a plausible chance of beating the incumbent. Consider the example where the voting figures were Con 60%, Lib 18%, Lab 17%, Green 5%. Is it selfish to vote expressively? Unless you believe that circumstances have changed sufficiently that one Conservative voter in six (surely that is a lot?) will switch allegiance, and that everyone, without exception, who voted for another party will support a single candidate, the result is not in doubt. Maybe voting expressively is a duty as it conveys information about who might be the best challenger in the long term.

    ReplyDelete

Unfortunately because of spam with embedded links (which then flag up warnings about the whole site on some browsers), I have to personally moderate all comments. As a result, your comment may not appear for some time. In addition, I cannot publish comments with links to websites because it takes too much time to check whether these sites are legitimate.