Paul Krugman’s post
which this responds to is described as wonkish, and so will this be. However,
if you are not an economist but are interested in economic methodology, you may
find this interesting even though I take some knowledge for granted.
Is
intertemporal optimisation at the heart of modern macro, as I wrote here,
or is it a gadget like the Dixit-Stiglitz model of monopolistic competition, as
Paul Krugman suggests here?
Well, I think I was right to characterise modern macro this way, but I also
agree with what I believe Professor Krugman was saying in his post. Let me
explain.
If we
were describing what particle physics is all about nowadays, we would probably not
say ‘building large Hadron Colliders’. We would say ‘looking for conjectured
but as yet unobserved fundamental particles’. Professor Krugman did not get a
Nobel for clever use of the Dixit-Stiglitz model of monopolistic competition,
but for investigating the role of increasing returns and imperfect competition
on trade and economic geography. So why characterise, as I did, modern macro by
a tool it uses (i.e. intertemporal optimisation), rather than by what it is
trying to achieve with that tool?
My
answer is as follows. Let’s define modern macro as starting with the New
Classical revolution of the 1970s. What I think singles out modern macro is not
what it is trying to explain, but how it tries to explain it. Intertemporal
optimisation is a tool that helps us understand (we hope) how people make
dynamic decisions (like how much to save), but trying to understand those
decisions did not start with the New Classical economists. What did begin in a
major way around then was the microfoundation of macroeconomics, which was a
major methodological change in how macroeconomics was done. So it seems quite
natural to say that this method is at the heart of modern macro.
But I
think Professor Krugman is pointing to a danger that results from this. He
writes “a gadget is only a gadget, and you should not let it define your field.”
If we define something by the tool or methods we use, we may start taking those
tools too seriously. Let me illustrate what I mean by an anecdote that deliberately
does not involve macro. I had a discussion many years ago with one of the UK’s
best microeconomists, who coincidentally (and from memory) was also inspired to
do economics by the same science fiction story
as Professor Krugman. Most wage bargaining models (at least at the time) made
the so called ‘right to manage’ assumption: there is bargaining over wages, but
firms determine employment. They make this assumption because that is what normally
happens in the real world. But, as a paper by
McDonald and Solow showed, this is inefficient. Both sides can be better off if they bargain over both wages and employment. My colleague was tempted (but only
tempted) to say that because of this result, maybe what appeared to be reality
was not in fact reality. After all, how could the actors involved not go for a
Pareto improvement?
Now just occasionally data is wrong, and what
appears to be reality is not. But 99.9% of the time this is the wrong response.
The right response is that the model is wrong. In this specific case the efficiency
result is missing an important aspect of the problem: it could be bargaining
costs and decision frequencies, or something even more
fundamental. But my point is that the temptation to take models too seriously
is often there. Going back to macro, I’ve sometimes heard it said by someone
that they are not sure how important price rigidity is, because they do not
find any of the models of price rigidity convincing. This is letting theory
define reality.
If that is Professor Krugman’s
point, then I agree with it. It is very similar to the argument I have
been making about the need to be pragmatic about microfoundations (post here,
article here),
and to be more open to macro that is not explicitly microfounded (post here).
Imagine a hypothetical history where we are doing macro at the end of the
1970s, but the microfoundations approach had already become established. Everything else is as it was: the main
Keynesian model of that time featured nominal rigidity due to (irrational)
inertia in expectations which could not be microfounded, and there were no alternative New Keynesian stories established. What do you do in
these circumstances? You should not carry on using microfounded models that ignore
price rigidity. Instead you should (a) look for a better microfounded model
that does allow price rigidity, but also (b) discount the microfounded models
you currently have because they are clearly incomplete/wrong, and (c) be
prepared to use the non-microfounded Keynesian model until something better
comes along.
So
while I think I was right to define modern macro by its methodology, I also
agree that this methodology can assume an importance that can be dangerous. I
think this is a danger that economics is particularly prone to, because its methodology
is essentially deductive in character, and economists are very attached to
their rationality axioms. The microfoundation of macroeconomic theory means
that macro is subject to that same danger. Ironically, just when microeconomics
is getting rather more relaxed about its axioms as a result of behavioural
economics in particular, the hegemony of microfoundations in macro is at its
height.
That
would be a nice way to end this post from a rhetorical point of view, but I
suspect if I did, some would misinterpret what I say as implying that the
majority of mainstream macroeconomists routinely make mistakes of this kind, or
worse still that the microfoundation of macro was a mistake. I believe neither
of those things, and I have been rather more positive
than Professor Krugman in the past on what modern macro has achieved. I hope it
is possible to be both supportive of modern macro and critical of it at the
same time.
Could you provide some examples of mechanisms that microfoundations helped to understand, or even better, policy recommendations that could be derived from microfoundations?
ReplyDeleteThere is no irony in this question. Even if I'm quite skeptical of microfoundations, I'm sure there are areas for which they provide a better understanding (...and others where they have the opposite effect).
I personally feel Macro needs to embrace 'class struggle' models to stay relevant.
ReplyDelete@Alex Volman most of the non-mainstream schools of thought do. I still think actual dynamic systems of differential equations seems like the most reasonable way to model the economy.
ReplyDelete"... its methodology is essentially deductive in character, and economists are very attached to their rationality axioms."
ReplyDeleteWhy do you believe that this is anything but a fatal flaw? After all, there does not exist any scientific discipline that has succeeded by following a purely deductive, axiomatic approach. Mathematics is not a science. Nor are metaphysics and theology.
And why do you feel that the existing microfoundations of macro are needed? You admit the microfoundations are fake and that they do nothing to resolve the Lucas critique. So two of the originally articulated reasons for them are rubbish. As to empirical successes, well, it is hard to think of something like the New Keynesian Phillips Curve as anything but an empirical embarrassment.
Simon, I'm sorry but you and many other hard core sticky price keynesians (I could find stuff to criticise about the indeterminacy Keynesian theorists like Roger Farmer, but it would be too long)are making it sound too easy. The issue isn't 1)whether some (a majority) of prices (or wages) are sticky. Of course they are. The question is given 1), 2) how much this affects aggregate outcomes in the economy. I'm surprised it's so obvious to some Kyenesians that 1) necessarily implies 2). After all, we all know that at the individual level housing investment is sticky in the sense that we move almost always when we have no choice (same for man durable goods like cars or TV's). Similarly, most of the employment decision is indivisible (despite the more continuously adjustable effort margin). Yet aggregate residential investment or durable investment are the most volatile components of GDP. And aggregate employment can also be quite volatile. So would you say the aggregate itself is sticky? This is not a trivial point, precisely because some of the most compelling models of micro level price rigidity suggest that this could be fully compatible with quite a flexible aggregate price level (I'm thinking of the search model of Burdett and Judd incorporated recently into a macro model by Randy Wright and co-authors, or models of long term customer relations). Talking of long term customer relations, the further complication is that price rigidity is often accompanied by quantity rigidity (the essence of long term contracts). But an environment in which quantities are also rigid when prices are rigid can end up behaving more like a flexible price environment than the standard Keyensian model where prices are rigid and quantities a freel adjusted given the price. I've waste too much time on this post. Should I mention the Barro critique, or in Robert Hall's wondeful phrase the Keyenesian put option assumption? Point is, as usual in macro, the data or casual real world observations are not enough to clearly discriminate theories with very different implications from each other.
ReplyDeleteAnd yet despite all that money has real effects...
DeleteAnd at that time Posst Keynesians disagreed with New Keynesians over the explanation for price rigidity and its relevance to the macroeconomics of Keynes. See "Price Rigidity in New Keynesianism and Post Keynesianism" for references
ReplyDeletehttp://socialdemocracy21stcentury.blogspot.com/2012/06/price-rigidity-in-new-keynesianism-and.html